Evolution thrives in systems with a
bottom-up organization, which gives rise to flexibility. But at the same time,
evolution has to channel the bottom-up approach in a way that doesn’t destroy the
organization. There has to be a hierarchy of control – with information flowing
from the bottom up as well as from the top down. The dynamics of complexity at
the edge of chaos seems to be ideal for this kind of behaviour (Doyne Farmer).
I introduced complex
adaptive systems (CASs) in Part 38. Then in Part 80 I described Langton's work on them; in
particular his introduction of the phrase 'edge of chaos' for the line in
phase space that separates ordered behaviour from chaotic behaviour, with
complex behaviour sandwiched between these two extremes. In 2-dimensional phase
space we need a line to separate the two regimes. In 3-dimensional space
we need a plane or a membrane (a 2-dimensional object) for effecting
this separation. In n-dimensional phase space we need an (n-1)-dimensional
hyper-membrane for separating ordered behaviour from chaotic behaviour. The
phrase 'edge of chaos' should be understood in this spirit.
We have seen in
Part 68 that even a simple computational algorithm
like the Game of Life is a universal computing device. The Game of Life is
independent of the computer used for running it, and exists in the Neumann
universe, just as other Class 4 CA do. They are capable of information
processing and data storage etc. They are a mixture of coherence and chaos.
They have enough stability to store information, and enough fluidity to
transmit signals over arbitrary distances in the Neumann universe.
There are many
analogies, not only with computation, but with life, economies, and social
systems also. After all, they are all just a series of computations. Life, for
example, is nothing if it cannot process information. And it strikes a right
balance between too static a behaviour and excessively chaotic or noisy
behaviour.
The occurrence
of complex phase-transition-like behaviour in the edge-of-chaos domain is
something very common in all branches of human knowledge. Kauffman (1969), for example,
recognized it in genetic regulatory networks (cf. Part 49). In his work
on such networks in the 1960s, he discovered that if the connections were too
sparse, the network would just settle down to a ‘dead’ configuration and stay
there. If the connections were too dense, there was a churning around in total
chaos. Only for an optimum density of connections did the stable state cycles arise.
Similarly, in
the mid-1980s, Farmer, Packard and Kauffman (1986) found in their autocatalytic-set model (cf.
Part 46) that when parameters such as the supply of
‘food’ molecules, and the catalytic strength of the chemical reactions etc.
were chosen arbitrarily, nothing much happened. Only for an optimum range of
these parameters did a ‘phase transition’ to autocatalytic behaviour set in
quickly.
Many more
examples can be given (Farmer et al.1986):
Coevolutionary systems, economies, social systems, etc. A right balance of
defence and combat in the coevolution of two antagonistic species ensures the
survival and propagation of both. Similarly, the health of economies and social
systems can be ensured only by a right mix of feedbacks and regulation on the
one hand, and plenty of flexibility and scope for creativity, innovation, and
response to new conditions, on the other. The dynamics of complexity around the
edge of chaos is ideally suited for evolution that does not destroy
self-organization.
Based on the
work of Kauffman, Langton, and many others, we can compile a number of
analogies or correspondences from a variety of disciplines. The table below
does just that. There is a gradation from (a) excessive order to (b) complex
creativity and progress to (c) total anarchy and failure. In each case there is
some kind of a ‘phase transition’ to the complexity regime as a function of
some control parameter (e.g. temperature in the case of second-order phase
transitions in crystals).
Cellular
automata classes
|
1 & 2 → 4 → 3
|
Dynamical
systems
|
Order → complexity
regime →
chaos
|
Matter
|
Solid →
phase-transition regime →
fluid
|
Computation
|
Halting →
undecidability regime →
nonhalting
|
Life
|
Too static → life /
intelligence →
too noisy
|
Genetic
networks
|
No activity →
stable-state cycles →
chaotic activity
|
Autocatalytic
sets of reactions
|
No
autocatalysis →
autocatalysis →
no autocatalysis
|
Coevolution
|
No
coevolution →
coevolution →
no coevolution
|
Economies,
social systems
|
No
creativity →
health and happiness →
anarchy
|
How do complex
systems move towards the edge-of-chaos regime, and then manage to stay there?
For complex adaptive systems (CAS), Holland (1975, 1995, 1998) provided an answer in terms of Darwinian
evolution. Complex systems that are capable of sophisticated behaviour have an
evolutionary advantage over systems that are too static and conservative or too
turbulent. Therefore both the latter categories would tend to evolve towards
the middle-course of complexity, if they are to survive at all. And once they
are in that regime, any deviations or fluctuations would tend to be reversed by
evolutionary factors.
The next
question is: What do complex systems do when they are at the edge of chaos.
Holland’s (1998) assertion about the occurrence of ‘perpetual
novelty’ in a CAS essentially amounts to saying that the system moves around in
the edge-of-chaos membrane in phase space. But that is not all. The moving
around actually takes the system to states of higher and higher sophistication
of structure and complexity. Learning and evolution not only take a CAS towards
the edge-of-chaos membrane, they also make it move in this membrane towards
states of higher complexity (Farmer et al.
1986 (cf. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Self-organization). The
ultimate reason for this, of course, is that the universe is ever expanding,
and there is therefore a perpetual input of free energy or negative entropy
into it.
Farmer gave
the example of the autocatalytic set model (which he proposed along with
Packard and Kauffman) to illustrate the point. When certain chemicals can
collectively catalyze the formation of one another, their concentrations increase
by a large factor spontaneously, far above the equilibrium values. This implies
that the set of chemicals as a whole emerges as a new ‘individual’ in a
far-from-equilibrium configuration. Such sets of chemicals can maintain and
propagate themselves, in spite of the
fact that there is no genetic code involved. In a set of experiments,
Farmer and colleagues tested the autocatalytic model further by allowing
occasionally for novel chemical reactions. Mostly such reactions caused the
autocatalytic set to crash or fall apart, but the ones that crashed made way
for a further evolutionary leap. New reaction pathways were triggered, and some
variations got amplified and stabilized. Of course, the stability lasted only
till the next crash. Thus a succession of autocatalytic metabolisms emerged.
Apparently, each level of emergence
through evolution and adaptation sets the stage for the next level of emergence
and organization.
NB (4 December 2014):
For an update, please click here.
NB (4 December 2014):
For an update, please click here.
No comments:
Post a Comment