The ability to reduce everything to simple fundamental laws does not imply the ability to start from those laws and reconstruct the universe. The constructionist hypothesis breaks down when confronted with the twin difficulties of scale and complexity. At each level of complexity entirely new properties appear. Psychology is not applied biology, nor is biology applied chemistry. We can now see that the whole becomes not merely more, but very different from the sum of its parts (Anderson 1972).
In complexity
science (and in philosophy), 'emergence' is a technical term. It signifies a breakdown
of the reductionistic approach usually
adopted in conventional science.
To give you a
feel for what emergence means, I shall explain why even the second law of
thermodynamics is actually an emergent law. The second law is something which every
macroscopic system must obey, in spite of the fact that the dynamics of the
individual microscopic constituents
of the system does not require that the law be obeyed. Because of this law, in
the macroscopic world in which we live, we take the direction of increasing
time as that in which the entropy of an isolated system increases and
irreversible processes occur. All macroscopic phenomena have the property of time-asymmetry.
I say that the
second law is an emergent law
because it is not deducible from the laws of mechanics obeyed by the microscopic
particles comprising a macroscopic system: The laws governing the dynamics of
the microscopic particles are time-symmetric,
at least in classical physics. Thus the time-asymmetry of the dynamics of such macroscopic
systems is an emergent property, not present at the microscopic level.
Similarly,
causality may be largely an emergent property, but I
must think about it some more.
The existence
of emergent laws has bothered several philosophers and scientists from times
immemorial. In fact it continues to do so. Many of them are still not able to
reconcile themselves to the very idea of emergence. Even Boltzmann, the
originator of statistical thermodynamics, did try for a while to reconcile the
time-symmetry of Newton’s equations of motion with the time-asymmetry inherent
in the second law. Starting from Newton’s equations of motion, Boltzmann did
succeed in achieving time-asymmetry in the nonlinear 'transport equation'
derived by him. The solution of this equation was the famous 'Boltzmann H function'. However, he soon realized that
although he had succeeded in deriving the occurrence of time-asymmetric
behaviour in a macroscopic system, he had introduced probability considerations for doing this, and this had serious
connotations regarding the nature of uncertainty.
He then went
to the other extreme, and approached the whole problem from the statistical
angle alone. But the equation derived by him for what we now call Boltzmann probability has a dynamical flavour. It is the probability
that a dynamical system will be in one of a given set of states, and is equal
to the fraction of the total observation time that the system spends in that
set of states.
Boltzmann’s
work met with stiff resistance and ridicule because his contemporaries just
could not accept emergence. The second law is a statistical law (cf. Part 22), and people
made a distinction between EXACT LAW which is never violated and STATISTICAL LAW which is practically never violated for a system of large number of
constituents. Boltzmann was very depressed by the response to his profound
work, and this possibly contributed to his suicide.
It has been
suggested by some scientists that the time-asymmetric nature of the second law
is partly a consequence of our inability to keep individual track of each of
the very large number of molecules (typically ~1023) in a
macroscopic system, implying that the origin of its time-asymmetric nature is statistical. But a better
rationalization can be achieved by probability-based arguments:
Let us refer
to the 'free expansion' figure I drew for Part 22, and which I
show here again:
In the left
part of this figure, all the molecules of the gas are in the left half, and
their positions and velocities are randomly distributed. At the moment the
partition is removed, there happens to be
a particular set of positions and velocities, which arose from a particular set
of initial conditions. It is important to realize that any other set of random
positions and velocities at that moment would still give the same irreversible
diffusion of the molecules to twice the volume. So this is a highly probable
thing to happen.
Now look at
the final configuration in which the gas has, on its own, occupied twice the volume.
The motion of each molecule is governed by time-symmetric laws of dynamics. If
we could somehow reverse the velocities of all the molecules at one particular
moment of time, they can go back to occupying the left half of the
chamber shown in the left part. But for this to happen the initial conditions,
or the boundary conditions, for all the ~1023 molecules will have to
be one particular set from among the infinite such sets of initial conditions,
and the probability for that to be the case is very very close to zero. That is
why irreversibility and time-asymmetry arise at the macroscopic level.
The second law
is an example of what is called WEAK
EMERGENCE. Although different parts of a macroscopic system are
interconnected, they are not necessarily interdependent.
If we select a smaller part of such a macroscopic system, the second law still
holds for it. Similarly, the pressure and temperature of a gas are emergent
properties, but only weakly emergent properties.
STRONG EMERGENCE, by contrast, is something for a
system as a whole. There is an interdependence among the various
subparts, and each part is indispensable for the overall emergent behaviour.
Strong
emergence is global. Weak emergence may be local.
Is space-time
an emergent property of the universe? Click HERE.
No comments:
Post a Comment